Wednesday, 28 May 2025

Can you write a thorough and nuanced account of Isabelle Stenger's thought?

ChatGPT said:

Certainly. Isabelle Stengers’ work is vast and complex, spanning philosophy of science, process philosophy, ecology, cosmopolitics, and political thought. Below is a structured overview of her thought, emphasizing key themes and concepts.


1. Science and the Question of Objectivity

Stengers critiques the traditional image of science as a neutral, objective enterprise. She challenges the idea that science is a transparent window onto reality, instead emphasizing its embeddedness in historical, social, and political conditions. She argues that scientific practices are not simply about "discovering" an independent world but involve world-making, shaping the very reality they claim to describe.

Her book The Invention of Modern Science (1993) offers a historical and philosophical critique of the epistemological assumptions underpinning modern science. She contends that science does not exist in a vacuum but is instead shaped by institutional, economic, and technological forces. However, unlike some radical social constructivists, she does not dismiss scientific knowledge. Instead, she seeks a more nuanced understanding that recognizes the entanglements between knowledge production and power.


2. Process Philosophy and Whiteheadian Influences

A crucial influence on Stengers is Alfred North Whitehead’s process philosophy. Whitehead rejects the notion of a static reality composed of inert substances, instead seeing reality as an ongoing process of becoming. Stengers takes up this perspective to challenge mechanistic and reductionist views of nature.

For Stengers, Whitehead offers a way out of the dualisms that structure modern thought: subject/object, nature/culture, mind/matter. She highlights his concept of "prehension"—the idea that entities do not passively receive information from the world but actively "grasp" and interpret their environment. This relational, event-based ontology opens up new ways of thinking about science, ethics, and politics.


3. Cosmopolitics: Beyond Human-Centered Thought

One of Stengers' most influential ideas is cosmopolitics, developed in Cosmopolitics I & II and other works. Unlike the traditional Kantian notion of cosmopolitanism, which is concerned with human political communities, Stengers’ cosmopolitics extends beyond the human. She argues that political thought must take into account not only human perspectives but also the perspectives of non-human entities, including animals, ecosystems, and even scientific objects.

Cosmopolitics is an attempt to resist the premature closure of debate in the name of objectivity. She criticizes the way scientific authority often forecloses alternative ways of knowing by presenting itself as the final arbiter of truth. Instead, she calls for a mode of inquiry that remains open to multiple perspectives, including indigenous knowledge, ecological concerns, and non-modern cosmologies.

A key cosmopolitical question is: How can we build a world together that is not based on domination, exclusion, or epistemological violence? This resonates with Donna Haraway’s concept of "staying with the trouble"—remaining with the tensions of complex entanglements rather than resolving them prematurely.


4. The Role of "Slowing Down" in Thought

Stengers argues that modernity is characterized by an accelerating, solution-oriented approach to knowledge and problem-solving. In contrast, she advocates for "slowing down" thought—pausing to consider the consequences, assumptions, and blind spots of our frameworks before rushing to act.

In Another Science is Possible (2013), she argues that scientists need to resist the pressures of neoliberalism, which demands rapid, market-driven innovation. She calls for an "ecology of practices," where different forms of knowledge (scientific, indigenous, artistic) can coexist and interact without one dominating the other.

Slowing down does not mean passivity but rather cultivating an ability to respond wisely to complex situations. This connects with her engagement with Deleuze and Guattari’s concept of the "rhizome"—a non-hierarchical, interconnected way of thinking that resists linear, reductionist models.


5. The Anthropocene and Ecological Thought

Stengers’ later work engages deeply with ecological crises and the Anthropocene. She rejects both apocalyptic fatalism and naive techno-optimism, instead advocating for a pragmatic, collective approach to ecological problems.

Her book In Catastrophic Times: Resisting the Coming Barbarism (2015) addresses the political and ethical challenges of climate change. She critiques the way environmental discourse is often framed in terms of urgency and emergency, which can lead to authoritarian solutions or paralyzing despair. Instead, she argues that we must learn to think differently about time, responsibility, and agency.

She is critical of the idea that science and technology alone can "solve" ecological problems, instead calling for a more situated, locally embedded approach that respects different forms of knowledge and ways of life.


6. Magic, Divination, and Alternative Rationalities

An unexpected but significant part of Stengers’ thought is her engagement with magic and divination. In Thinking with Whitehead (2002), she provocatively suggests that divinatory practices, rather than being dismissed as superstitions, offer alternative ways of engaging with the world. She is not advocating for a return to pre-modern magical thinking but rather questioning why certain modes of knowledge (such as science) are granted unquestioned authority while others are marginalized.

This connects to her broader interest in how different forms of knowledge relate to power. She does not claim that all knowledge systems are equally valid but insists that we must interrogate the exclusions and hierarchies built into modern epistemology.


7. Political and Ethical Implications

Stengers’ work has profound implications for politics and ethics. Her emphasis on process, relation, and multiplicity leads to an ethics of responsibility rather than certainty. She challenges the idea that there are universal solutions to political problems, instead advocating for situated, context-sensitive engagements.

Her critique of modern science and technology is not anti-science but rather a call for a more democratic and pluralistic approach to knowledge. She argues that the way we frame problems determines the kinds of solutions we consider possible. By resisting premature closure, she opens space for new ways of thinking and acting.

Her work also intersects with feminist, decolonial, and indigenous critiques of Western epistemology. She aligns with thinkers like Donna Haraway, Eduardo Viveiros de Castro, and Anna Tsing in advocating for a more relational, less anthropocentric way of understanding the world.


Conclusion: Stengers as a Thinker of Possibility

Isabelle Stengers is a philosopher of resistance, creativity, and possibility. She challenges dominant paradigms without falling into nihilism or relativism. Her process-oriented, cosmopolitical approach offers a way of thinking that is attuned to complexity, plurality, and the unfinished nature of reality.

In an era of ecological crisis, political instability, and epistemic fragmentation, her work provides tools for rethinking our relationships with science, politics, and the more-than-human world. By slowing down, staying with complexity, and remaining open to alternative ways of knowing, Stengers offers a vision of thought that is both rigorous and generative—a philosophy that does not seek to master the world but to engage with it responsibly.


Would you like me to expand on any particular aspect?

You said:

Her book _The Invention of Modern Science_ (1993) offers a historical and philosophical critique of the epistemological assumptions underpinning modern science. She contends that science does not exist in a vacuum but is instead shaped by institutional, economic, and technological forces. However, unlike some radical social constructivists, she does not dismiss scientific knowledge. Instead, she seeks a more nuanced understanding that recognizes the entanglements between knowledge production and power.



How does this differ from Foucault exactly?
ChatGPT said:

The key difference between Isabelle Stengers and Michel Foucault here lies in how they conceptualize the relationship between science, power, and reality.

Foucault: Science as a Regime of Truth

Foucault’s work on science—particularly in The Order of Things, Discipline and Punish, and The Birth of the Clinic—focuses on how scientific knowledge is historically contingent and embedded in episteme (historical structures of knowledge) or dispositifs (networks of power and discourse). He argues that science is not a neutral or objective pursuit but is shaped by institutional forces and power relations. In his genealogical works, he emphasizes how disciplines such as medicine, psychiatry, and criminology establish "regimes of truth"—specific ways of organizing knowledge that determine what counts as valid knowledge and who has the authority to speak.

For Foucault, knowledge is always implicated in power, and scientific discourse functions as a means of social control. The sciences, especially the human sciences, do not merely "discover" truths about the world; they actively shape and constitute the very objects they claim to describe—whether it be madness, sexuality, or criminality. His work leans toward an anti-foundationalist stance: scientific truth is never "outside" of power but is always embedded in historical struggles.

Stengers: Science as a World-Making Practice, Not Just a Power Structure

Stengers shares Foucault’s skepticism of science as an unquestioned authority, but she does not reduce science to a mere instrument of power. Unlike Foucault’s genealogical approach, which often highlights how knowledge disciplines and governs, Stengers is interested in how knowledge is produced through processes of experimentation and engagement with reality.

  • She does not see science as a pure reflection of reality nor as a pure discursive construct. Instead, she sees scientific practices as "world-making": they actively shape the reality they describe, but they are also constrained by the material world.

  • While Foucault might emphasize how power organizes knowledge (who gets to speak, what counts as truth, how knowledge disciplines), Stengers is more interested in the internal dynamics of scientific practice—the contingencies, failures, and creative processes involved in scientific work.

  • She wants to slow down scientific thought—not to debunk it, but to give it room to become more pluralistic, responsive, and self-critical.

Key Distinctions

AspectFoucaultStengers
Science’s Relationship to PowerScience is deeply embedded in power structures and functions as a regime of truth. It disciplines subjects and organizes social life.Science is shaped by institutions and power but is also a site of creative, experimental engagement with the world.
Ontology of ScienceScience does not reflect a pre-given reality but constructs objects of knowledge through discourse and power relations.Science participates in "world-making," engaging with material processes and realities while remaining socially and historically embedded.
Critique of ScienceScience functions as a disciplinary apparatus, structuring what can be said and known.Science is not dismissed but needs to be situated—understood in its ecological, social, and political entanglements.
Epistemological PositionAnti-foundationalist: knowledge is always contingent and shaped by discourse.Processual and pragmatic: knowledge is an ongoing, situated engagement with an evolving reality.

A More Generous View of Science?

While Foucault focuses on how science functions as a disciplinary force, Stengers is more sympathetic to the idea that science can be a creative, experimental process that interacts with reality in ways not reducible to power relations alone. This is why she is more aligned with Whitehead than with Foucauldian critique: she believes that science is more than just a political technology—it is also a way of engaging with an evolving, relational world.

Would you like me to refine this further?

You said:

Science is shaped by institutions and power but is also a site of creative, experimental engagement with the world.

But didn't Foucault also see power and knowledge as generative? Also, when he writes about the plague he thinks that the Black plague happened. He simply focusses on what surrounds an event or thing rather than on the event itself.
ChatGPT said:

You're absolutely right. Foucault does not reduce power to repression; he sees it as productive, generative, and immanent to social relations. His concept of power-knowledge (pouvoir-savoir) suggests that knowledge does not merely reflect the world but actively constitutes it. When he analyzes something like the plague, he acknowledges that the plague happened—he is not denying its material reality—but he is more concerned with the epistemic and institutional responses that structure how the event is managed, understood, and made meaningful.

So How Does This Differ from Stengers?

The key difference is what they focus on within the entanglement of power, knowledge, and reality.

  • Foucault focuses on how power organizes knowledge and produces social subjects—how discourses shape the way we experience and categorize reality. His method is primarily archaeological and genealogical, tracing how discourses and institutions emerge, change, and discipline the world.

  • Stengers focuses on how knowledge practices engage with an evolving, processual reality—not just the institutional structuring of knowledge but also how knowledge itself is an encounter with a world that resists, surprises, and pushes back.

Example: The Plague

  • Foucault (in Discipline and Punish): The plague is a biological event, but what interests him is how it serves as an occasion for the emergence of disciplinary power. The plague justifies surveillance, quarantine, and new administrative techniques that later become generalizable to other aspects of governance.

  • Stengers (if she were to analyze the plague): She would be more interested in how different forms of knowledge—scientific, medical, indigenous, magical—engage with the plague as a dynamic event. How does scientific knowledge evolve in response to the plague? How do different knowledge systems interact in the face of catastrophe?

Foucault’s interest is in how discourse governs the world, while Stengers is more interested in how practices engage with a world that exceeds discourse. This is why she aligns more with Whitehead: for her, knowledge is never just a structure of power but an unfolding process of relation—where scientists, experiments, and even non-human entities play an active role in shaping reality.

No comments:

1. Annulment of the Subject/Object Binary Whitehead does not accept a static subject/object dichotomy. Instead, he sees all actual entitie...