"To never forget your own insignificance. To never get used to the unspeakable violence and the vulgar disparity of life around you. To seek joy in the saddest places...To never simplify what is complicated or complicate what is simple. To respect strength, never power. Above all, to watch. To try and understand. To never look away and never, never, to forget." ~ Arundhati Roy
Tuesday, 3 September 2024
Liberalism and the Discipline of Power
"The charge used to be leveled by fascists and communists; now
it comes chiefly from conservatives. Liberalism, they say, is a kind of
weakness. If the charge were true—if liberal institutions and political
leaders were unequal to the demands of national defense and personal
security—it would have been a catastrophe for liberal democracy dur-
ing the great crises of the twentieth century, and the world would look
altogether different today. But this has not been the historical experi-
ence: liberal government has repeatedly proved stronger and more
durable than its adversaries expected. And therein lies a critical lesson
about liberalism, at least liberalism rightly understood.
The core principles of liberalism provide not only a theory of freedom,
equality, and the public good, but also a discipline of power—the means
of creating power as well as controlling it. This discipline has been a sin-
gular achievement of constitutional liberalism, dating from the late sev-
enteenth and eighteenth centuries, and of modern, democratic liberalism
as it has evolved roughly since the late nineteenth century.
Liberal constitutions impose constraints on the power of any single
public official or branch of government as well as the state as a whole.
The constraints protect citizens from tyranny, but that is not all they
do. They also serve to protect the state itself from capricious, impulsive,
or overreaching decisions. A central insight of liberalism is that power
arbitrarily exercised is destructive not only of individual liberty but also
of the rule of law. Limiting arbitrary power encourages confidence that
the law will be fair and thereby increases the state’s ability to secure co-
operation without the imposition of force. Limiting the scope of state
power increases the likelihood of its effective use as well as the ability of
society to generate wealth, knowledge, and other resources that a state
may draw upon in an hour of need. That, at least, has been the theory of
power—of freedom’s power—implicit in constitutional liberalism. And
the historic rise of liberal states to become the most powerful in the
world suggests that the theory has worked astonishingly well in practice.
Constitutional liberalism is the common heritage of both modern
conservatives and liberals, as those terms are understood in the Anglo-
American world. In the eighteenth century, however, constitutional
liberalism was far from fully democratic. Britain and the early Ameri-
can republic excluded the majority of people from the franchise and
other rights, and even after working-class men gained the right to vote,
liberal governments in Europe and North America continued to reject
the claims of women and racial minorities. Modern democratic liberal-
ism diverged from its conservative sibling, however, as it embraced the
claims of historically excluded groups and a more comprehensive vision
of equality. Even with the basic disputes over the franchise and civil
rights long resolved, the line between liberalism and conservatism con-
tinues to be drawn partly on this basis.
In addition, modern liberals have split from conservatives on the role
of the state in the face of depression, war, and economic insecurity. Liber-
als have insisted that government can take on broader functions without
sacrificing individual freedom as long as the law provides strong safe-
guards against arbitrary power. Democratic liberalism, therefore, has
called not just for broader social protections but also for stronger guaran-
tees of civil liberties. Conservatives and liberals have also responded dif-
ferently to a phenomenon that did not exist in the eighteenth century
when constitutional liberalism took shape: the modern corporation.
While conservatives have treated private corporations as analogous to
individuals and deserving of the same liberties, liberals have regarded
corporations as a phenomenon of power, needing control like govern-
ment itself. The discipline of power that constitutional liberalism im-
16 FREEDOM’S POWER
046508186X 01.qxd 12/27/06 9:40 AM Page 16
poses upon the state modern liberalism attempts to impose on the corpo-
ration, albeit not in the same way.
Divisions between conservatives and liberals over foreign policy and
national security also reflect different theories of power. In general, con-
servatives have put greater emphasis on military power, been quicker to
resort to force, and regarded international institutions warily, whereas
liberals have sought to create an international order that helps to safe-
guard national sovereignty, enlarges the sphere of liberal democracy, and
minimizes the need for force. While conservatives have often regarded
international law and institutions as subtracting from national power,
liberals have seen them as adding to it. Just as liberalism has historically
sought to protect individual rights through the rule of law and limits on
unbridled power at home, so it has sought to project those same norms of
respect for law, life, and liberty into the international arena—conscious,
however, that force may ultimately be necessary for self-defense and that
force spent unwisely may undermine security rather than ensure it.
In short, like constitutional liberalism, modern democratic liberalism
seeks to promote the creation as well as the control of power. Rights for
the unpropertied, racial minorities, and women are not simply a check on
the powerful; full inclusion also promotes a more creative and productive
society. The expanded sphere of state action has enabled liberal govern-
ments to contend successfully with war and other crises and to promote
economic growth and stability. In disciplining the market as well as the
state, the central liberal objective has been not just to circumscribe power
in private hands, but also to make the market more productive within its
appropriate scope. A liberal international order promises to conserve and
augment national power as well as properly regulate it. Power disciplined
is not necessarily power reduced. Discipline may impart greater legiti-
macy, a sharpened focus, and more judicious direction to power—to a
kind of power, moreover, that supports freedom instead of destroying it.
POWER AND LIBERTY
Power is essential to liberty, yet power is also inimical to liberty—it all
depends on the kind of power and its use, and on our understanding of
liberty. In a generic sense, power is the capacity of an individual, group,
state, or some other agent to bring about effects. Power in this general
sense—“power to”—encompasses whatever capacity a society or any
other collectivity may have to realize common values or purposes. To
say that an individual or some other agent is powerful, however, usually
means that it can bring about one particular kind of result: It can pre-
vail over others—it can get them to do something they do not want to
do, defeat them in a conflict, or perhaps even shape their understand-
ing and desires.1
Whether this kind of power—“power over”—is compatible with lib-
erty depends on whether it is subject to law, norms of fairness, and pub-
lic accountability. Liberal principles for the discipline of power have a
threefold purpose: to constrain “power over” that is arbitrary, despotic,
and overweening; to establish rules for the legitimate exercise of power;
and to enlarge the overall capacities of both individuals and societies.
The central liberal hypothesis about power is that constraints on des-
potic “power over” contribute to greater societal “power to.” Or, as the
political theorist Stephen Holmes has put it, limited power can be
“more powerful than unlimited power.”2
Liberal constitutions, for example, call for checks and balances, pub-
lic deliberation, periodic elections, and other institutional mechanisms
to prevent state power from becoming despotic. But constitutions are
not purely negative in purpose or effect. They also provide a plan for
the exercise of legitimate powers and a conceptual framework for poli-
tics. Indeed, constitutions may become the very basis of national iden-
tity and patriotism and thereby an instrument for building nations as
well as their governments. Or to put it in other terms, some constitu-
tions are constitutive of both a nation and its state, not merely regula-
tive of a state’s conduct.
If well designed, liberal constitutions create states with advantages in
power and performance over their illiberal rivals. Public deliberation in-
vites ideas and information that autocrats do not receive or are unlikely
to heed. A state with checks and balances and public accountability for
governmental performance will be more likely to correct its mistakes.
And those who lose political conflicts after discussion and voting are
more likely to be reconciled to the outcome and to cooperate with the
winners than if they are excluded from participation. To be sure, public
deliberation may slow down decisionmaking in urgent situations, and
elections may produce inconclusive results. The art of constitutional de-
sign lies partly in minimizing the chances of paralysis where decisions
are imperative. The liberal premise is that although these risks are real,
the advantages of constitutional government outweigh them.
Liberal principles also aim to bar private forms of despotic power by,
for example, prohibiting slavery and regulating predatory and abusive
aspects of commercial and even domestic relationships. Again, laws
embodying liberal principles are not purely negative; to some extent,
they also prescribe rules for legitimate transactions and relationships to
ensure that they are entered into freely and observe minimum stan-
dards of fairness. Moreover, just as liberal principles call for checks and
balances within government, so they call for a wide dispersion of power
in both the private economy and civil society. Concentrations of pri-
vate power undermine the effort to keep political power divided and
limited; hence, even apart from concerns about economic efficiency,
liberals from the eighteenth century to the present have often called
for breaking up monopolies, broadening the ownership of land, and ex-
tending literacy and education.
These commitments follow from the recognition that liberty is most
likely to be preserved when citizens themselves have the power to pre-
serve it. When freedom does its work, it creates a self-reinforcing cycle.
Free speech and freedom of association, for example, empower civil so-
ciety, and the private organizations that grow up on that basis can then
use their power to sustain their rights. Newspapers, for example, be-
come jealous guardians of the freedom of the press. But monopoly turns
this process on its head; if the press itself becomes monopolized, those
who control it may become too great an arbiter of political life, inhibit-
ing free discussion rather than enabling it. Modern democratic liberal-
ism differs from its free-market rival partly in its support for stronger
measures to decentralize private power and stronger guarantees against
private forms of domination—for example, by calling for countervailing
rights to private corporations, such as the rights of workers to collective
bargaining and of consumers to information about corporate practices.
In the same spirit, modern liberalism has also sought to extend to the
private economy guarantees of equal treatment of racial and religious
minorities, women, and other groups that have historically suffered
from discrimination.
These measures to decentralize and limit private power and to com-
bat discrimination require state intervention in the private decisions
made in the market and civil society. But liberalism, according to some
of its exponents and many of its critics, conceives of liberty only as
non-interference by the state. This notion may suggest that liberals re-
sist state power at every instant, despite the manifest fact that liberal
states have been immensely powerful. The conception of liberty as non-
interference does fit libertarian thought, but it does not express the full
understanding of liberty and power even in the classical liberalism of
the eighteenth century, much less in its modern democratic forms.
Liberty is a species of power—the power to make choices about what
is rightfully yours, free of removable hindrances.3 But while anxious to
guard a sphere of individual choice and private life from state control,
liberalism has never stood for the anarchist and romantic view that all
state power is inherently repressive. Liberals have typically supported
a state strong enough, at a minimum, to defend itself against external
enemies, to enforce the rule of law, to provide for public goods inade-
quately produced in the marketplace, to control anticompetitive prac-
tices, and to uphold the rights of individuals against such internal
threats to their liberty as private oligarchs, local overlords, and reli-
gious sects or clans capable of fanatical cruelty toward each other and
their own members.
It is not only to the state that liberals are concerned liberty may be
lost. Rights of free speech and free assembly also vanish where the fear
of mobs or thugs prevents people from speaking freely or meeting to-
gether. Weak states undermine the foundations of liberty as much as the
foundations of order; even “negative liberty” depends on the state’s
active presence in society, not merely on the “silence” of the law. Rights
have no meaning except within the context of a state capable of up-
holding them. No state, no rights. No law, no liberty.
But by the same token, modern liberalism holds that insofar as gov-
ernment acquires more power, it ought to be held accountable, checked
internally, and balanced by a countervailing recognition of rights.
Modern liberalism does not sacrifice liberty to power. It raises the equi-
librium of power and liberty to a higher level.
HOW LIBERALISM WORKS
Much political analysis assumes that if one group or individual has
more power, others must have less, and that is true in certain contexts.
In a war, greater military power on one side necessarily means less
power on the other. But not all social life is war. Some social arrange-
ments make it possible to expand the sum of social power, particularly
over time. Liberal states have been precisely that—exceptionally pro-
ductive systems of power creation.
Law lies at the base of this system, simultaneously constraining
power and enlarging it. The rule of law—a first principle of liberalism,
though not exclusive to it—demands, among other things, that laws be
general, public, unalterable retroactively, and applied the same regard-
less of the individuals involved. 4 These requirements, insofar as they
are realized in practice, give individuals leverage to resist arbitrary acts
of state, but states also derive a benefit from them. By upholding the
rule of law, including a commitment to apply the law to themselves,
rulers may be better able to attract investment, obtain credit, and sus-
tain popular loyalty and cooperation. They may also be able to reduce
power-depleting rivalries among clans and factions by convincing them
that the state represents an impartial arbiter of their claims and dis-
couraging those who feel wronged from adopting private alternatives to
law, such as by seeking revenge for crimes or personal affronts. Where
private vengeance rules, some individuals or groups certainly have
more power than others—they can prevail over them. But violent
feuds deplete society of the power necessary to achieve collective ends.
The rule of law offers an alternative to private justice that instead of
consuming power increases it.
The rule of law also offers a model of how states can advance indi-
vidual liberty along with societal powers. For when the law is general,
public, stable, and so on, individuals are not only less subject to arbi-
trary power but also at greater liberty to plan their lives. And insofar as
their plans include long-term investments, the society may be more
prosperous and the state capable of raising greater revenue. This is the
virtuous cycle of power and liberty that the rule of law allows and that
constitutional liberalism ideally extends.
In a different way, guarantees of religious toleration and freedom of
conscience exemplify the logic of liberalism as a foundation for a stable
polity. Internecine religious conflicts and wars of religion, like revenge
feuds, deplete the powers of states and societies. Religious toleration
serves not only to allow people to worship differently but also to reduce
conflict, facilitate economic exchange, and create a wider pool of talent
for productive work and the state itself. By dividing religion from law—
that is, by excluding religion from any binding social consensus—states
guaranteeing religious freedom allow people of different faiths to coop-
erate under a political order that does not threaten to extinguish any of
the various theological doctrines they support.
Religious toleration has also served as a paradigm for the state’s ac-
ceptance of pluralism in other cultural and moral controversies. Where
divisions over the meaning of the good life are deep and irreconcilable,
the state’s neutrality among competing perspectives furthers mutual for-
bearance, cooperation, and the growth of societal powers. The neutral-
ity of the liberal state, however, does not apply to all matters of moral
judgment. Liberalism not only regards people as worthy of being treated
equally but holds that each individual life has positive value, and the
laws and policies of a liberal state ought to embody that principle,
though citizens may well disagree about how to interpret it. As each life
has value, so do the health and well-being of the community: liberal
policies in support of public health and a salubrious and sustainable en-
vironment stem from commitments that are moral in their inspiration.
And because education necessarily cultivates character as well as in-
telligence, a liberal society will properly use its schools to pass on to the
young such moral qualities as integrity, perseverance, empathy, and
personal and civic responsibility. But just as liberalism excludes religion
from a binding social consensus, so it accepts a diversity of cultural and
moral practices that cause no harm to others. The framework of a lib-
eral society is only a framework—that is, it provides space for free de-
velopment, allowing for differences and promoting cooperation. We
may justify religious freedom and cultural diversity on the grounds of
individual rights and autonomy or the equal respect due people of dif-
ferent faiths and values. But the potential of liberty to promote stable
cooperation and state power helps to explain why states that adopted
religious toleration continued to maintain it and why they have ex-
panded the scope of pluralism.
These kinds of effects on societal power are crucial in accounting for
liberalism’s historical rise. The liberal hypothesis is not that each and
every constraint on power serves the utilitarian purpose of enlarging so-
cietal powers, much less that every rule should be tested solely on that
criterion. Rather, the hypothesis is that liberal constraints on power,
when taken as a whole, have created stronger self-corrective political
mechanisms, a more innovative and productive economy, broader so-
cietal cooperation, and other formidable advantages. Mechanisms of
this kind help to explain why liberal ideas became the basis of enduring
liberal states.
046508186X 01.qxd 12/27/06 9:40 AM Page 25
much of continental Europe as monarchs increasingly governed by pre-
rogative and effectively put the traditional consultative assemblies to
sleep. England remained the great exception to this pattern. The lib-
eral theory of constitutionalism, as developed by Locke, Montesquieu,
and the American founders, drew on the English tradition but involved
more than a reassertion of checks on executive power and demand for
the rule of law. Constitutional liberalism called for generalizing and ex-
tending such principles as separation of powers and guarantees of life,
liberty, and property far beyond their old boundaries.6
England, the United States, and France exemplified three different
paths toward constitutional liberalism. The English acquired their
liberties—the plural is important here—through a long process of accre-
tion, without any single comprehensive or abstract formulation. By the
late seventeenth century, they conceived of their unwritten constitu-
tion as a balance among king, lords, and commons that protected their
liberties while maintaining harmony, hierarchy, and order. This consti-
tution, however, existed only as an inference from the laws; it did not
antedate or stand above them, and thus it could be changed through or-
dinary legislation. Working within this framework, English liberalism
sought, one reform at a time, to eliminate the legal vestiges of feudalism,
to extend the sphere of individual liberty, and, if not to limit the state,
then to subject its expansion to a constitutional discipline.
The United States built its legal system on English foundations, in-
corporating English liberties into the Bill of Rights and adopting the
common law, but Americans radically changed the idea of a constitu-
tion. They invented the practice of writing constitutions through spe-
cially convened assemblies and submitting them to public discussion
and ratification. The U.S. Constitution, unlike England’s, prospec-
tively created the state, established the conceptual framework of poli-
tics, and became a regulative standard above ordinary legislation. In
proposing and adopting a comprehensive structure of government cre-
ated afresh, America’s founding generation displayed a breathtaking
confidence in the human capacity for rational design of the state that
was utterly foreign to the English belief in the cumulative genius of po-
litical tradition. In the Declaration of Independence, the Americans of
the Revolutionary era also inscribed abstract ideals of liberty and equal-
ity into their national creed. In short, while English constitutionalism
grew out of the historical and particular, American constitutionalism
added to it elements that were rational and universal.
The French Revolution took that rationalism and universality one
step further, repudiating the traditional liberties of the Old Regime as
mere privileges and overthrowing them entirely in the name of abstract
ideals of liberty and equality. In the same spirit, France’s revolutionaries
saw the Anglo-American devotion to separation of powers as a medi-
eval vestige and placed full sovereignty in a single assembly. But the
Revolution’s uprooted abstractions and unified structure of the popular
will proved no protection against terror and despotism. In the United
States, constitutional liberalism was the legacy of a successful revolu-
tion that became the basis of a national creed (although it would take
the Civil War to overcome the contradiction between slavery and free-
dom that had been left unresolved at the nation’s founding). In France,
constitutional liberals were merely a political faction during most of
the nineteenth century, and constitutional liberalism remained the dis-
puted lesson of a revolution that had failed to institutionalize itself.
The conservative reaction triggered by the French Revolution and
its aftermath weighed heavily on liberalism in England and on the con-
tinent well into the nineteenth century. Liberal parties generally sub-
scribed to the principles of religious toleration and constitutional
government, but in the wake of the French Revolution they tended to
be wary of democracy and to interpret political liberties such as free
speech in narrow terms. The cause that became of greatest importance
to them was economic freedom. With the rise of classical economics
and laissez-faire came a conception of liberalism as being devoted to an
ideal of negative liberty and a general hostility to the state. But this
economic liberalism of the nineteenth century represented a shift from
the more complex view of the state expressed in earlier liberal political
thought. Constitutional liberalism sought both to create and to con-
tain power.''
Subscribe to:
Post Comments (Atom)
Patronizing behavior stems from a complex mix of social dynamics, power imbalances, and individual insecurities. It can be subtle or overt, ...
-
Like a Tangled Mobile A susceptibility to the appeal of authoritarian irrationalism has become part of what it means to be a modern pers...
-
Why are you standing on hot coals? So called civil society is hostile to every form of life. It's not just genocidal, it's geocidal....
-
'' So long as community always attests to a constituent body, it attests to the carnage that keeps it firmly intelligible. As Be...
No comments:
Post a Comment