This is a powerful and dense articulation of the way aesthetics, particularly as aisthēsis, is both a site of capture and a latent site of liberation. The critique of pure feeling and the shift from cause-and-effect to cause-and-affect aligns with a broader process-relational move: rejecting a mechanistic model of reality in favor of one where relational dynamics, perception, and transformation are fundamental.
Stiegler’s notion of the capture of symbols by economic warfare is especially relevant here, as it directly implicates planetary computation. If planetary computation is not just an infrastructure but also an epistemic condition—one that organizes perception, knowledge, and action—then its role in the aesthetic and affective domain is critical. Who or what mediates what is felt and how it is felt determines the possible futures that can even be imagined, let alone enacted.
This passage also sharpens a political critique: while a privileged few engage in aesthetic inquiry, the many are consigned to a brutalized symbolic economy where signs, affects, and categories are weaponized. The list—stereotypes, stigmas, presentism, obliviousness, etc.—maps out an entire ecology of disorientation. That disorientation is not incidental but a deliberate effect of symbolic warfare, producing individuals and collectives unable to navigate, resist, or even conceptualize alternatives.
What remains, then, is the question of how aesthetics as a practice can break from this condition. Is it through counter-systems of mediation, a radical rethinking of technê, or a retrieval of aisthēsis in its full relational and communal sense? Do you see planetary computation as complicit in this symbolic war, or could it be leveraged toward a reactivation of the latent potential you describe?
The idea that aesthetics, if freed, could generate "realisable visions or senses of better worlds" is not foreign to Stiegler but is something he tends to approach more cautiously—he often focuses more on the problem of loss and disindividuation rather than positing clear paths to liberation.
Stiegler did indeed write about public art and aesthetics as a potential site of individuation and liberation, particularly in relation to neganthropology and the reconstitution of collective attention. He saw aesthetics—when properly cultivated—as a means of resisting symbolic capture and fostering a renewed sense of shared sensibility.
However, he was also deeply concerned with how contemporary aesthetics had been expropriated by industries that induce proletarianization (the loss of individual and collective capacities for interpretation and invention). His discussions often emphasized the difficulty of recovering aesthetic practices from the grip of hyper-industrialized media, consumerism, and the automation of perception.
So while he did see aesthetic practices—especially public art—as crucial for reconstituting savoir-faire (know-how) and savoir-vivre (know-how-to-live), he was skeptical of easy solutions. His work suggests that any attempt to reclaim aesthetics must also involve a technological and economic transformation, not just an artistic or philosophical one.
Your reading, then, is quite fair—Stiegler did hold that aesthetics, if freed, could help generate realizable visions of better worlds. But he likely would have stressed that this potential remains fragile and precarious, requiring a struggle against the very forces that have immiserated it. Would you like to add more of this tension into your formulation, or do you think your version already captures enough of his ambivalence?
You said:
ChatGPT said:
That’s fair—Stiegler’s work is dense and sprawling, weaving together philosophy, economics, technology, and aesthetics in complex ways. If you’re interested, I can help clarify specific aspects of his thought or suggest key texts that might make his ideas more accessible. Would you like a concise breakdown of his core arguments on aesthetics, individuation, and symbolic capture?
You said:
disindividuation
ChatGPT said:
In Bernard Stiegler’s view, disindividuation is primarily caused by the exploitation of attention in an environment dominated by industrially produced media, advertising, and digital technologies. These systems, which Stiegler often refers to as technics and industries of attention, act as mechanisms that fragment or diminish individual and collective capacities for deeper reflection, autonomy, and meaningful engagement with the world.
Key causes of disindividuation in Stiegler’s thought include:
-
Industrialization of Culture: The mass production of cultural artifacts and the commodification of aesthetics, particularly through media industries (film, television, advertising, digital platforms), leads to the standardization of experience and the loss of individual and collective capacities to critically engage with the world.
-
Technological Mediation of Desire and Attention: With the rise of digital technologies, particularly social media and algorithm-driven platforms, attention has become a valuable resource that is continuously captured, redirected, and manipulated. The technologies of attention undermine the ability to think critically, leading to a kind of passive reception of external stimuli rather than active individuation through personal reflection and engagement.
-
Loss of Symbolic Capital: Stiegler argues that the process of symbolic capture—where meaning, culture, and symbols are captured and repurposed by powerful economic forces—prevents the development of individual subjectivity. This transformation of symbols into commodities erodes the ability to create new, meaningful cultural practices or to reappropriate symbols in ways that foster autonomous thinking and social transformation.
-
Acceleration of Technological Change: The rapid pace of technological change and the obsolescence of older ways of being (especially in relation to the individual’s sense of time and embodied experience) disorients people and causes a sense of alienation. This technological acceleration doesn't just affect material conditions but also the way people relate to their own desires, goals, and possibilities for action.
In short, disindividuation is driven by external, technological forces that fragment and manipulate human attention, alienate individuals from their own capacities for critical thought and creativity, and foster a form of collective subjectivity that is more responsive to market logic than to personal or communal development.
Does this resonate with your sense of the dynamics you were reading about, or would you like to dive deeper into any particular element of this?
You said:
neganthropology
ChatGPT said:
Neganthropology is a term coined by Stiegler to describe the study of human beings in relation to technics (tools, technologies, and systems of knowledge) with a focus on how technology shapes human evolution, both positively and negatively. The term comes from the idea of neganthropy, which combines "negative" and "anthropology"—meaning the study of the ways in which humans have been disindividuated or degraded by technological processes, as well as the potential for technology to help reconstitute or individualize human beings in meaningful ways.
Stiegler uses neganthropology to explore how technological development has simultaneously shaped and undermined human individuality and collective life. He critiques the tendency for contemporary technologies, especially digital technologies, to disempower and disorient individuals by commodifying attention and stripping people of their ability to form meaningful, autonomous relationships with the world. However, he also sees the potential for a positive neganthropy, where the same technological forces could be harnessed to re-individuate or reconstitute human beings in ways that promote personal and collective autonomy, creativity, and reflective thought.
At its core, neganthropology is about understanding both the destructive and constructive roles that technology plays in the development of human subjectivity. It considers how humans have been shaped by their tools in both regressive (disindividuation) and progressive (individuation and transformation) ways.
Bernard Stiegler does engage with the concept of aisthēsis, although he interprets it in the context of his broader critique of technology and culture. Aisthēsis (Greek for "sensation" or "perception") in Stiegler’s thought refers to the fundamental process of sensing and experiencing the world, but he uses it not just in a purely aesthetic or sensory sense. Instead, he incorporates it into his analysis of the relationship between humans and their technologies, particularly in how technology shapes our collective and individual experience of the world.
Stiegler often ties aisthēsis to sympathy—the capacity to feel with others or to perceive the world in a communal, relational way. This aligns with his focus on the communal nature of perception and experience, which, in turn, connects to his critique of disindividuation. In a world where technology commodifies attention and experiences, the capacity for aisthēsis is undermined or captured by industries of attention (such as advertising and social media).
Aesthetic Practices and Technics:
For Stiegler, aesthetic practices (which are grounded in aisthēsis) have the potential to resist this capture. When approached as practices of collective sensibility, these forms of aesthetic engagement—whether through art, music, or other expressions—can generate new forms of social and individual individuation (the process of becoming a more fully realized person). This ties directly into Stiegler’s vision of a renewed, critical engagement with technologies to counteract the disindividuating forces that he sees as pervasive in contemporary society.
Symbolic Capture and Aisthēsis:
However, he is also highly critical of the way that modern industries (like the entertainment industry) have captured aisthēsis—making it into a commodity that serves capitalist interests rather than fostering authentic, reflective experiences. This symbolic capture, where art and culture are increasingly produced for profit rather than personal or collective transformation, contributes to the degradation of aisthēsis, turning it into a passive, manipulated form of experience.
In sum, Stiegler’s use of aisthēsis focuses on its potential as a communal, transformative experience but acknowledges how it has been distorted or diminished by modern technological and economic systems. It’s integral to his broader argument that we need to reclaim and reimagine these sensory and aesthetic practices as a way to resist disindividuation and create new, more meaningful relations to the world.
No comments:
Post a Comment