Writing for the 7th Circuit in 1995, Judge Richard Posner, a self-appointed
protector of the interests of business, applied cost/benefit analysis to the ADA:
If the nation’s employers have potentially unlimited financial obligations to
43 million disabled persons, the Americans with Disabilities Act will have
imposed an indirect tax potentially greater than the national debt. We do
not find an intention to bring about such a radical result in either the
language of the Act or its history. The preamble actually ‘markets’ the Act
as a cost saver, pointing to ‘billions of dollars in unnecessary expenses
resulting from dependency and nonproductivity’. The savings will be illusory if
employers are required to expend many more billions in
accommodation than will be saved by enabling disabled people to work.72
The cost-benefit view (whether real or perceived) of the business class at large
runs up against their political representatives’ expectations in sponsoring the
ADA. Those who believe that liberal civil rights are the solution to the unemployment
predicament of disabled people confront the problem that within
capitalism equal treatment is in contradiction with macro-economic realities.
Unemployment is a permanent feature of any capitalist economy. Civil rights,
though still necessary to counter individual acts of prejudice and discrimination,
have only the power (if enforced) to randomly distribute the maladies of unemployment,
income and wage inequality throughout the population,73 not to meet
everyone’s material needs. Is there social justice in promoting bourgeois liberal
remedies that may liberate some but not all disabled persons from oppression?
Liberal anti-discrimination laws cannot end systemic unemployment and individual
rights cannot override the economic structure. Neither the market nor
civil rights laws can end the exclusion of disabled people from the labour force.
Business has obtained both the legal and political legitimacy necessary to
discriminate and exclude millions from the workforce in the name of work-place
and market efficiency.74 Transforming this reality, not the (unachievable) accommodation
of disabilities under a liberal ‘rights’ model, must clearly be a goal of
any socialist praxis worthy of its name.
So how, then, can disability politics help to end capitalist exploitation? While
to address this question fully is beyond the scope of this paper we will offer some
food for thought. Oliver, for instance, suggests ‘if the game is possessive individualism
in a competitive and inegalitarian society, impaired people will
inevitably be disadvantaged, no matter how the rules are changed’.75 Finkelstein
recognizes that a society may be willing to absorb a portion of its impaired population
into the workforce, yet this can have the effect of maintaining and perhaps
intensifying the exclusion of the remainder.76 Indeed, former US President
Clinton suggested that bringing disabled persons into the workforce could be a
tool to fight inflation in a tight labour market.77 Abberley suggests that we
abandon the notion that production be at the centre of any new conceptualization
of Utopia: ‘even in a society which did make profound and genuine attempts
to integrate impaired people into the world of work, some would still be
excluded by their impairment’.78
But need the ability to labour in some socially recognized sense be a requirement for full
membership in society? In a work-based society, productivism is the
‘normal’ activity. A radical disability perspective could offer great liberatory
potential by proposing to abolish this notion and to offer counter-values to those
of productivism. Is work the defining quality of our worth? Employability, aptitude
for earning money and even work chosen during one’s free time are not, a
priori, the measure of what it means to live, to be part of the human race.
Moreover, a counter-hegemonic praxis of disability politics, challenging productivism,
opens the door to alliances with many other groups who are also
marginalized by the imprisoning dictates of a market economy. These include
single mothers, welfare recipients, part-time workers, parts of the incarcerated
population, and all those unable for various reasons to earn a living wage. Indeed,
the fostering of grassroots solidarity amongst those oppressed by productionism
can only serve to enrich the disability rights movements themselves and enhance
the chances of achieving reformist goals of physical and structural access while
pursuing a longer term agenda of economic transformation. After all, what is the
alternative? Eugenics, sterilization, euthanasia and the institutionalization of the
impaired and others have all been productivist societies’ answers to what to do
with the ‘unproductive’. If the goal of social justice is to ensure the dignity of each
and every person, then buying into the largely capitalist-induced belief that work
equates with self esteem or is a condition for membership of the human race —
that people are labourers first and human beings second — only serves to oppress
us all.
No comments:
Post a Comment